IBN SINA
ABU ALI
AL-HUSAYN (980-1037)
Ibn Sina
(Avicenna) is one of the foremost philosophers in the Medieval Hellenistic Islamic
tradition that also includes al-Farabi and Ibn Rushd His philosophical theory is a
comprehensive, detailed and rationalistic account of the nature of God and Being, in which
he finds a systematic place for the corporeal world, spirit, insight, and the varieties of
logical thought including dialectic, rhetoric and poetry.
Central to Ibn
Sinas philosophy is his concept of reality and reasoning. Reason, in his scheme, can
allow progress through various levels of understanding and can finally lead to God, the
ultimate truth. He stresses the importance of gaining knowledge, and develops a theory of
knowledge based on four faculties: sense perception, retention, imagination and
estimation. Imagination has the principal role in intellection, as it can compare and
construct images which give it access to universals. Again the ultimate object of
knowledge is God, the pure intellect.
In metaphysics, Ibn Sina makes a distinction between essence and existence; essence considers only the nature of things, and should be considered apart from their mental and physical realization. This distinction applies to all things except God, whom Ibn Sina identifies as the first cause and therefore both essence and existence. He also argued that the soul is incorporeal and cannot be destroyed. The soul, in his view, is an agent with choice in this world between good and evil, which in turn leads to reward or punishment.
Reference has
sometimes been made to Ibn Sinas supposed mysticism, but this would appear to be
based on a misreading by Western philosophers of parts of his work. As one of the most
important practitioners of philosophy, Ibn Sina exercised a strong influence over both
other Islamic philosophers and medieval Europe. His work was one of the main targets of
al-Ghazalis attack on Hellenistic influences in Islam. In Latin translations, his
works influenced many Christian philosophers, most notably Thomas Aquinas.
6 The soul
8 Poetry, character and society
References
and further reading
Ibn Sina was
born in AH 370/AD 980 near Bukhara in Central Asia, where his father governed a village in
one of the royal estates. At thirteen, Ibn Sina began a study of medicine that resulted in
distinguished physicians . . . reading the science of medicine under [him]
(Sirat al-shaykh al-rais (The Life of Ibn Sina): 27). His medical expertise brought
him to the attention of the Sultan of Bukhara, Nuh ibn Mansur, whom he treated
successfully; as a result he was given permission to use the sultans library and its
rare manuscripts, allowing him to continue his research into modes of knowledge.
When the sultan
died, the heir to the throne, Ali ibn Shams al-Dawla, asked Ibn Sina to continue al
vizier, but the philosopher was negotiating to join the forces of another son of the late
king, Ala al-Dawla, and so went into hiding. During this time he composed his major
philosophical treatise, Kitab al-shifa (Book
of Healing), a comprehensive account of learning that ranges from logic and mathematics to
metaphysics and the afterlife. While he was writing the section on logic Ibn Sina was
arrested and imprisoned, but he escaped to Isfahan, disguised as a Sufi, and joined Ala
al-Dawla. While in the service of the latter he completed al-Shifa and produced the Kitab al-najat (Book of Salvation), an abridgment
of al-Shifa. He also produced at least two
major works on logic: one, al-Mantiq, translated
as The Propositional Logic of Ibn Sina, was a
commentary on Aristotles Prior Analytics and
forms part of al-Shifa; the other, al-Isharat wa-I-tanbihat (Remarks and
Admonitions), seems to be written in the indicative mode, where the reader
must participate by working out the steps leading from the stated premises to proposed
conclusions. He also produced a treatise on definitions and a summary of the theoretical
sciences, together with a number of psychological, religious and other works; the latter
include works on astronomy, medicine, philology and zoology, as well as poems and an
allegorical work, Hayy ibn Yaqzan (The Living
Son of the Vigilant). His biographer also mentions numerous short works on logic and
metaphysics, and a book on Fair Judgment that was lost when his princes
fortunes suffered a turn. Ibn Sinas philosophical and medical work and his political
involvement continued until his death.
Ibn Sinas
autobiography parallels his allegorical work, Hayy
ibn Yaqzan. Both clarify how it is possible for individuals by themselves to arrive at
the ultimate truths about reality, being and God. The autobiography shows how Ibn Sina
more or less taught himself, although with particular kinds of help at significant
moments, and proceeded through various levels of sophistication until he arrived at
ultimate truths.
Such progress was
possible because of Ibn Sinas conception of reality and reasoning. He maintains that
God, the principle of all existence, is pure intellect, from whom other existing things
such as minds, bodies and other objects all emanate, and therefore to whom they are all
necessarily related. That necessity, once it is fully understood, is rational and allows
existents to be inferred from each other and, ultimately, from God. In effect, the
totality of intelligibles is structured syllogistically and human knowledge consists of
the minds reception and grasp of intelligible being. Since knowledge consists of
grasping syllogistically structured intelligibles, it requires the use of reasoning to
follow the relations between intelligibles. Among these intelligibles are first principles
that include both concepts such as the existent, the thing and
the necessary, that make up the categories, and the truths of logic, including
the first-figure syllogistics, all of which are basic, primitive and obvious. They cannot
be explained further since all explanation and thought proceeds only on their basis. The
rules of logic are also crucial to human development.
Ibn Sinas
stand on the fundamental nature of categorical concepts and logical forms follows central
features of Aristotles thought in the Prior Analytics (see ARISTOTLE §§4-7).
Borrowing from Aristotle, he also singles out a capacity for a mental act in which the
knower spontaneously hits upon the middle term of a syllogism. Since rational arguments
proceed syllogistically, the ability to hit upon the middle term is the ability to move an
argument forward by seeing how given premises yield appropriate conclusions. It allows the
person possessing this ability to develop arguments, to recognize the inferential
relations between syllogisms. Moreover, since reality is structured syllogistically, the
ability to hit upon the middle term and to develop arguments is crucial to moving
knowledge of reality forward.
Ibn Sina holds
that it is important to gain knowledge. Grasp of the intelligibles determines the fate of
the rational soul in the hereafter, and therefore is crucial to human activity. When the
human intellect grasps these intelligibles it comes into contact with the Active
Intellect, a level of being that emanates ultimately from God, and receives a divine
effluence. People may be ordered according to their capacity for gaining knowledge,
and thus by their possession and development of the capacity for hitting on the middle
term. At the highest point is the prophet, who knows the intelligibles all at once, or
nearly so. He has a pure rational soul and can know the intelligibles in their proper
syllogistic order, including their middle terms. At the other end lies the impure person
lacking in the capacity for developing arguments. Most people are in between these
extremes, but they may improve their capacity for grasping the middle term by developing a
balanced temperament and purity of soul (see LOGIC IN ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY §1).
In relation to the
older debate about the respective scopes of grammar and logic, Ibn Sina argues that since
logic deals with concepts that can be abstracted from sensible material, it also escapes
the contingencies of the latter. Language and grammar govern sensible material and
therefore have a different domain; indeed, languages are various and their rules of
operation, their grasp of sensible material, are likewise articulated variously (see
LANGUAGE, PHILOSOPHY OF). Nevertheless, languages make available the abstracted concepts
whose operation is governed by logic; yet if language deals with contingencies, it is not
clear how it can grasp or make available the objects of logic. At times, as for example in
al-Isharat, Ibn Sina suggests that languages
generally share a structure.
In his theory of
knowledge, Ibn Sina identifies the mental faculties of the soul in terms of their
epistemological function. As the discussion of logic in §2 has already suggested,
knowledge begins with abstraction. Sense perception, being already mental, is the form of
the object perceived (see SENSE AND REFERENCE §I). Sense perception responds to the
particular with its given form and material accidents. As a mental event, being a
perception of an object rather than the object itself, perception occurs in the
particular. To analyse this response, classifying its formal features in abstraction from
material accidents, we must both retain the images given by sensation and also manipulate
them by disconnecting parts and aligning them according to their formal and other
properties. However, retention and manipulation are distinct epistemological functions,
and cannot depend on the same psychological faculty; therefore Ibn Sina distinguishes
faculties of relation and manipulation as appropriate to those diverse epistemological
functions (see EPISTEMOLOGY IN ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY §4).
Ibn Sina
identifies the retentive faculty as representation and charges the imagination
with the task of reproducing and manipulating images. To conceptualize our experience and
to order it according to its qualities, we must have and be able to reinvoke images of
what we experienced but is now absent. For this we need sensation and representation at
least; in addition, to order and classify the content of representation, we must be able
to discriminate, separate out and recombine parts of images, and therefore must possess
imagination and reason. To think about a black flag we must be able to analyse its colour,
separating this quality from others, or its part in the image from other images, and
classify it with other black things, thereby showing that the concept of black applies to
all such objects and their images. Imagination carries out this manipulation, allowing us
to produce images of objects we have not seen in fact out of the images of things we have
experienced, and thereby also generating images for intelligibles and prophecies.
Beyond sense
perception, retention and imagination, Ibn Sina locates estimation (wahm). This is a faculty for perceiving
non-sensible intentions that exist in the individual sensible objects. A sheep
flees a wolf because it estimates that the animal may do it harm; this estimation is more
than representation and imagination, since it includes an intention that is additional to
the perceived and abstracted form and concept of the animal. Finally, there may be a
faculty that retains the content of wahm, the
meanings of images. Ibn Sina also relies on a faculty of common sense, involving awareness
of the work and products of all the other faculties, which interrelates these features.
Of these
faculties, imagination has a principal role in intellection. Its comparison and
construction of images with given meanings gives it access to universals in that it is
able to think of the universal by manipulating images (see UNIVERSALS). However, Ibn Sina
explains this process of grasping the universal, this emergence of the universal in the
human mind, as the result of an action on the mind by the Active Intellect. This intellect
is the last of ten cosmic intellects that stand below God. In other words, the
manipulation of images does not by itself procure a grasp of universals so much as train
the mind to think the universals when they are given to the mind by the Active Intellect.
Once achieved, the processes undergone in training inform the mind so that the latter can
attend directly to the Active Intellect when required. Such direct access is crucial since
the soul lacks any faculty for retaining universals and therefore repeatedly needs fresh
access to the Active Intellect.
As the highest
point above the Active Intellect, God, the pure intellect, is also the highest object of
human knowledge. All sense experience, logic and the faculties of the human soul are
therefore directed at grasping the fundamental structure of reality as it emanates from
that source and, through various levels of being down to the Active Intellect, becomes
available to human thought through reason or, in the case of prophets, intuition. By this
conception, then, there is a close relation between logic, thought, experience, the grasp
of the ultimate structure of reality and an understanding of God. As the highest and
purest intellect, God is the source of all the existent things in the world. The latter
emanate from that pure high intellect, and they are ordered according to a necessity that
we can grasp by the use of rational conceptual thought (see NEOPLATONISM IN ISLAMIC
PHILOSOPHY). These interconnections become clearer in Ibn Sinas metaphysics.
Metaphysics
examines existence as such, absolute existence (al-wujud al-matlaq) or existence so far as it
exists. Ibn Sina relies on the one hand on the distinction in Aristotles Prior Analytics between the principles basic to a
scientific or mathematical grasp of the world, including the four causes, and on the other
hand the subject of metaphysics, the prime or ultimate cause of all things - God. In
relation to the first issue, Ibn Sina recognizes that observation of regularities in
nature fails to establish their necessity. At best it evinces the existence of a relation
of concomitance between events. To establish the necessity implicated in causality, we
must recognize that merely accidental regularities would be unlikely to occur always, or
even at all, and certainly not with the regularity that events can exhibit (see CAUSALITY
AND NECESSITY IN ISLAMIC THOUGHT). Thus, we may expect that such regularities must be the
necessary result of the essential properties of the objects in question.
In developing this
distinction between the principles and subject of metaphysics, Ibn Sina makes another
distinction between essence and existence, one that applies to everything except God.
Essence and existence are distinct in that we cannot infer from the essence of something
that it must exist (see EXISTENCE). Essence considers only the nature of things, and while
this may be realized in particular real circumstances or as an item in the mind with its
attendant conditions, nevertheless essence can be considered for itself apart from that
mental and physical realization. Essences exist in supra-human intelligences and also in
the human mind. Further, if essence is distinct from existence in the way Ibn Sina is
proposing, then both the existence and the nonexistence of the essence may occur, and each
may call for explanation.
The above
distinctions enter into the central subject matter of metaphysics, that is, God and the
proof of his existence. Scholars propose that the most detailed and comprehensive of Ibn
Sinas arguments for Gods existence occurs in the Metaphysics
section of al-Shifa (Gutas 1988; Mamura 1962; Morewedge 1972). We know from the Categories of Aristotle that existence is either
necessary or possible. If an existence were only possible, then we could argue that it
would presuppose a necessary existence, for as a merely possible existence, it need not
have existed and would need some additional factor to bring about its existence rather
than its non-existence. That is, the possible existence, in order to be existent, must
have been necessitated by something else. Yet that something else cannot be another merely
possible existence since the latter would itself stand in need of some other necessitation
in order to bring it about. or would lead to an infinite regress without explaining why
the merely possible existence does exist. From this point, Ibn Sina proposes that an
essential cause and its effect will coexist and cannot be part of an infinite chain; the
nexus of causes and effects must have a first cause, which exists necessarily for itself:
God (see GOD, ARGUMENTS FOR THE EXISTENCE OF § I ).
From his proof of
Gods existence. Ibn Sina goes on to explain how the world and its order emanates
from God. Whereas ARISTOTLE (§ 16) himself did not relate the Active Intellect that may
be implied in On the Soul III with the first,
ever-thinking cause of the universal found in Book XII of his Metaphysics, later
commentators on his work (for example, ALEXANDER OF APHRODISIAS) identified the two,
making the Active Intellect, the principle that brings about the passage of the human
intellect from possibility to actuality, into the first cause of the universe. Together
with this is the proof of Gods existence that sees him not only as the prime mover
but also as the first existent. Gods self-knowledge consist in an eternal act that
results in or brings about a first intelligence or awareness. This first intelligence
conceives or cognizes the necessity of Gods existence, the necessity of its own
existence, and its own existence as possible. From these acts of conception, other
existents arise: another intelligence, a celestial soul and a celestial body,
respectively. The last constitutes the first sphere of the universe, and when the second
intelligence engages in its own cognitive act, it constitutes the level of fixed stars as
well as another level of intelligence that, in turn, produces another intelligence and
another level of body. The last such intelligence that emanates from the successive acts
of knowing is the Active Intellect, that produces our world. Such emanation cannot
continue indefinitely; although being may proceed from intelligence, not every
intelligence containing the same aspects will produce the same effects. Successive
intelligences have diminished power. and the active intellect, standing tenth in the
hierarchy, no longer possesses the power to emanate eternal beings.
None of these
proposals by Ibn Sina give grounds for supposing that he was committed to mysticism (for
an opposing view, see MYSTICAL PHILOSOPHY IN ISLAM § I). His so called Eastern
philosophy, usually understood to contain his mystical doctrines, seems to be an
entirely Western invention that over the last two hundred years has been read into Ibn
Sinas work (see Gutas 1988). Nevertheless, Ibn Sina combines his Aristotelianism
with a religious interest, seeking to explain prophecy as having its basis in a direct
openness of the prophets mind to the Active Intellect, through which the middle
terms of syllogisms, the syllogisms themselves and their conclusions become available
without the procedure of working out proofs. Sometimes the prophet gains insight through
imagination, and expresses his insight in figurative terms. It is also possible for the
imagination to gain contact with the souls of the higher spheres, allowing the prophet to
envisage the future in some figurative form. There may also be other varieties of
prophecy.
In all these
dealings with prophecy, knowledge and metaphysics, Ibn Sina takes it that the entity
involved is the human soul. In al-Shifa, he
proposes that the soul must be an incorporeal substance because intellectual thoughts
themselves are indivisible. Presumably he means that a coherent thought, involving
concepts in some determinate order, cannot be had in parts by different intellects and
still remain a single coherent thought. In order to be a coherent single unity, a coherent
thought must be had by a single, unified intellect rather than, for example, one intellect
having one part of the thought, another soul a separate part of the thought and yet a
third intellect having a third distinct part of the same thought. In other words, a
coherent thought is indivisible and can be present as such only to an intellect that is
similarly unified or indivisible. However, corporeal matter is divisible; therefore the
indivisible intellect that is necessary for coherent thought cannot be corporeal. It must
therefore be incorporeal, since those are the only two available possibilities.
For Ibn Sina, that
the soul is incorporeal implies also that it must be immortal: the decay and destruction
of the body does not affect the soul. There are basically three relations to the corporeal
body that might also threaten the soul but, Ibn Sina proposes, none of these relations
holds true of the incorporeal soul, which therefore must be immortal. If the body were a
cause of the souls existence, or if body and soul depended on each other necessarily
for their existence, or if the soul logically depended on the body, then the destruction
or decay of the body would determine the existence of the soul. However, the body is not a
cause of the soul in any of the four senses of cause; both are substances, corporeal and
incorporeal, and therefore as substances they must be independent of each other; and the
body changes and decays as a result of its independent causes and substances, not because
of changes in the soul, and therefore it does not follow that any change in the body,
including death, must determine the existence of the soul. Even if the emergence of the
human soul implies a role for the body, the role of this corporeal matter is only
accidental.
To this
explanation that the destruction of the body does not entail or cause the destruction of
the soul, Ibn Sina adds an argument that the destruction of the soul cannot be caused by
anything. Composite existing objects are subject to destruction; by contrast, the soul as
a simple incorporeal being is not subject to destruction. Moreover, since the soul is not
a compound of matter and form, it may be generated but it does not suffer the destruction
that afflicts all generated things that are composed of form and matter. Similarly, even
if we could identify the soul as a compound, for it to have unity that compound must
itself be integrated as a unity, and the principle of this unity of the soul must be
simple; and, so far as the principle involves an ontological commitment to existence,
being simple and incorporeal it must therefore be indestructible (see SOUL IN ISLAMIC
PHILOSOPHY).
From the
indestructibility of the soul arise questions about the character of the soul, what the
soul may expect in a world emanating from God, and what its position will be in the cosmic
system. Since Ibn Sina maintains that souls retain their identity into immortality, we may
also ask about their destiny and how this is determined. Finally, since Ibn Sina also
wants to ascribe punishment and reward to such souls, he needs to explain how there may be
both destiny and punishment.
The need for
punishment depends on the possibility of evil, and Ibn Sinas examination maintains
that moral and other evils afflict individuals rather than species. Evils are usually an
accidental result of things that otherwise produce good. God produces more good than evil
when he produces this sublunary world, and abandoning an overwhelmingly good practice
because of a rare evil would be a privation of good. For example, fire is
useful and therefore good, even if it harms people on occasion (see EVIL, PROBLEM OF). God
might have created a world in another existence that was entirely free of the evil present
in this one, but that would preclude all the greater goods available in this world,
despite the rare evil it also contains. Thus, God generates a world that contains good and
evil and the agent, the soul. acts in this world; the rewards and punishments it gains in
its existence beyond this world are the result of its choices in this world, and there can
be both destiny and punishment because the world and its order are precisely what give
souls a choice between good and evil.
8 Poetry,
character and society
Identifying
poetic language as imaginative, Ibn Sina relies on the ability of the faculty of
imagination to construct images to argue that poetic language can bear a distinction
between premises, argument and conclusion, and allows for a conception of poetic
syllogism. Aristotles definition of a syllogism was that if certain statements are
accepted, then certain other statements must also necessarily be accepted (see ARISTOTLE
§5). To explain this syllogistic structure of poetic language, Ibn Sina first identifies
poetic premises as resemblances formed by poets that
produce an astonishing effect of distress or pleasure (see POETRY).
The resemblances
essayed by poets and the comparisons they put forward in poems, when these are striking,
original and so on, produce an astonishing effect or feeling of
wonder in the listener or reader. The evening of life compares the spans
of a day and a life, bringing the connotations of the day to explain some characteristics
of a lifespan. To find this use of poetic language meaningful, the suggestion is that we
need to see the comparison as the conclusion of a syllogism. A premise of this syllogism
would be that days have a span that resembles or is comparable to the progression of a
life. This resemblance is striking, novel and insightful, and understanding its
juxtaposition of days and lives leads subjects to feel wonder or astonishment. Next,
pleasure occurs in this consideration of the poetic syllogism as the basis of our
imaginative assent, paralleling assent in, for example, the demonstrative syllogism: once
we have accepted the premise, we are led to accept the associations and imaginative
constructions that result; once we accept the comparison between days and lives, we can
understand and appreciate the comparison between old age and evening. Ibn Sina also finds
other parallels between poetic language and meaningful arguments, showing that pleasure in
imaginative assent can be expected of other subjects; assent is therefore more than an
expression of personal preferences. This validity of poetic language makes it possible for
Ibn Sina to argue that beauty in poetic language has a moral value that sustains and
depends on relations of justice between autonomous members of a community. In his
commentary on Aristotles Poetics, however, he combines this with a claim that
different kinds of poetic language will suit different kinds of characters. Comedy suits
people who are base and uncouth. while tragedy attracts an audience of noble characters
(see AESTHETICS IN ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY).
Latin versions
of some of Ibn Sinas works began to appear in the early thirteenth century. The best
known philosophical work to be translated was his Kitab
al-shifa, although the translation did not include the sections on mathematics
or large sections of the logic. Translations made at Toledo include the Kitab al-najat and the Kitab al-ilahiyat (Metaphysics) in its entirety.
Other sections on natural science were translated at Burgos and for the King of Sicily.
GERARD OF CREMONA translated Ibn Sinas al-Qanun
f1-tibb (Canon on Medicine). At Barcelona, another philosophical work, part of
the Kitab al-nafs (Book of the Soul), was translated early in the fourteenth
century. His late work on logic, al-Isharat
wa-l-tanbihat, seems to have been translated in part and is cited in other
works. His commentaries on On the Soul were
known to Thomas AQUINAS and ALBERT THE GREAT, who cite them extensively in their own
discussions.
These and other
translations of Ibn Sinas works made up the core of a body of literature that was
available for study. By the early thirteenth century, his works were studied not only in
relation to Neoplatonists such as AUGUSTINE and DUNS SCOTUS, but were used also in study
of ARISTOTLE. Consequently, they were banned in 1210 when the synod at Paris prohibited
the reading of Aristotle and of summae and commenta of his work.
The force of the ban was local and only covered the teaching of this subject: the texts
were read and taught at Toulouse in 1229. As late as the sixteenth century there were
other translations of short works by Ibn Sina into Latin, for example by Andrea Alpago of
Belluno (see ARISTOTELIANISM, MEDIEVAL §3; ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY: TRANSMISSION INTO WESTERN
EUROPE; TRANSLATORS).
See also: AESTHETICS IN
ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY; ARISTOTELIANISM IN ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY; EPISTEMOLOGY IN ISLAMIC
PHILOSOPHY; LOGIC IN ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY; SOUL IN ISLAMIC
PHILOSOPHY; ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY:
TRANSMISSION INTO WESTERN EUROPE
Ibn Sina
(980-1037) Sirat al-shaykh al-rais (The
Life of Ibn Sina), ed. and trans. WE. Gohlman, Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press, 1974. (The only critical edition of Ibn Sinas autobiography, supplemented
with material from a biography by his student Abu Ubayd al-Juzjani. A more recent
translation of the Autobiography appears in D. Gutas, Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition: Introduction
to Reading Avicennas Philosophical Works, Leiden: Brill, 1988.)
- (980-1037) al-Isharat wa-l-tanbihat (Remarks and
Admonitions), ed. S. Dunya, Cairo, 1960; parts translated by S.C. Inati, Remarks and Admonitions, Part One: Logic, Toronto,
Ont.: Pontifical Institute for Mediaeval Studies, 1984, and Ibn Sina and Mysticism, Remarks and Admonitions: Part
4, London: Kegan Paul International, 1996. (The English translation is very useful for
what it shows of the philosophers conception of logic, the varieties of syllogism,
premises and so on.)
- (980-1037) al-Qanun fil-tibb (Canon on Medicine), ed.
I. a-Qashsh, Cairo, 1987. (Ibn Sinas work on medicine.)
(980-1037) Risalah fi sirr
al-qadar (Essay on the Secret of Destiny), trans. G. Hourani in Reason and Tradition in Islamic Ethics, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1985. (Provides insights into a neglected area of Ibn
Sinas thought.)
(980-1037) Danishnama-i alai (The Book of
Scientific Knowledge), ed. and trans. P Morewedge, The
Metaphysics of Avicenna, London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1973. (This is a translation of a metaphysical work in Persian.)
- (c 1014-20) al-Shifa (Healing). (Ibn Sinas major
work on philosophy. He probably began to compose al-Shifa
in 1014, and completed it in 1020. Critical editions of the Arabic text have been
published in Cairo, 1952-83, originally under the supervision of I. Madkour; some of these
editions are given below.)
- (c.1014-20) al-Mantiq (Logic), Part 1, alMadkhal (Isag6ge), ed. G. Anawati, M.
El-Khodeiri and F. al-Ahwani, Cairo: al-Matbaah al-Amiriyah, 1952; trans. N.
Shehaby, The Propositional Logic of Ibn Sina, Dordrecht:
Reidel, 1973. (Volume I, Part 1
of al-Shifa.)
- (c 1014-20) al-Ibarah (Interpretation), ed. M.
El-Khodeiri, Cairo: Dar al-Katib al-Arabi, 1970. (Volume 1, Part 3 of al-Shifa.)
- (c 1014-20) al-Qiyas (Syllogism), ed. S. Zayed and I. Madkour,
Cairo: Organisme General des Imprimeries Gouvernementales, 1964. (Volume I, Part 4 of al-Shifa.)
- (c 1014-20) al-Burhan (Demonstration), ed. A.E. Affifi, Cairo:
Organisme General des Imprimeries Gouvernementales, 1956. (Volume I, Part 5 of
al-Shifa.)
(c 1014-20)
al-Jadal (Dialectic), ed. A.F Al-Ehwany, Cairo: Organisme General des Imprimeries
Gouvernementales, 1965. (Volume I, Part 7 of
al-Shifa.)
- (c 1014-20) al-Khatabah (Rhetoric), ed. S. Salim, Cairo:
Imprimerie Nationale, 1954. (Volume I, Part 8 of al-Shifa.)
- (c.1014-20) al-Ilahiyat (Theology), ed. M.Y. Moussa, S. Dunya
and S. Zayed, Cairo: Organisme General des Imprimeries Gouvernementales, 1960; ed. and
trans. R.M. Savory and D. A. Agius, Ibn Sina on Primary Concepts in the Metaphysics of al-Shifa, in Logikos Islamikos, Toronto, Ont.: Pontifical
Institute for Mediaeval Studies, 1984; trans. G.C. Anawati, La metaphysique du Shifa, Etudes Musulmanes
21, 27, Paris: Vrin, 1978, 1985. (This is the metaphysics of al-Shifa, Volume I, Book 5.)
- (c 1014-20) al-Nafs (The Soul), ed. G.C. Anawati and S. Zayed,
Cairo: Organisme General des Imprimeries Gouvernementales, 1975; ed. F. Rahman, Avicennas De Anima, Being the Psychological Part
of Kitab al-Shifa, London: Oxford University Press, 1959. (Volume 1, part 6 of al-Shifa.)
- (c 1014-20) Kitab al-najat (The Book of Salvation), trans. F.
Rahman, Avicennas Psychology: An English
Translation of Kitab al-Najat, Book II, Chapter VI with Historical-philosophical Notes and
Textual Improvements on the Cairo Edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1952. (The
pyschology of al-Shifa.)
References and
further reading
* Alexander of Aphrodisias (c 200) De anima (On the Soul), in Scripta minora 2.1, ed. I. Bruns, Berlin, 1887; ed.
A.P. Fontinis, The De Anima of Alexander of
Aphrodisias, Washington, DC: University Press of
America, 1979. (Important later commentary on Aristotle.)
Davidson, H.A.
(1992) Alfarabi, Avicenna and Averroes on Intellect:
Their Cosmologies, Theories of the Active Intellect, and Theories of the Human Intellect, New
York: Oxford University Press (A thorough consideration of Ibn Sinas theory of the intellects in relation to Hellenistic and
Arabic philosophers.)
Fakhry, M.
(1993) Ethical Theories in Islam, 2nd edn,
Leiden: Brill. (Contains material on Ibn Sinas ethical thought.)
Goodman, L.
(1992) Avicenna, London: Routledge. (A useful
introduction to central features of Ibn Sinas philosophical theories.)
* Gutas, D.
(1988) Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition,
Introduction to Reading Avicennas Philosophical Works, Leiden: Brill. (An
excellent account of the considerations that entered into the construction of Ibn
Sinas corpus, the book contains
translations of a number of smaller texts, a careful consideration of method and sharp
criticisms of, among other things, ascriptions of mysticism to Ibn Sina. This is probably
the most useful guide to an engagement with the philosophers work currently
available in English.)
Inati, S. (1996)
Ibn Sina, in S.H. Nasr and O, Leaman (eds) History of Islamic Philosophy, London: Routledge,
ch. 16, 231-L6. (Comprehensive guide to his analytical thought.)
Janssens, J.L.
(1991) An Annotated Bibliography on Ibn Sina
(1970-1989), Including Arabic and Persian Publications and Turkish and Russian references,
Leuven: University of Leuven Press. (An indispensible tool for study of Ibn Sina and
recent work on the philosopher, though it will soon need to be updated.)
Kemal, S. (1991)
The Poetics of Alfarabi and Avicenna, Leiden:
Brill. (A philosophical study of Ibn Sinas philosophical poetics and its relation to
epistemology and morality.)
* Mamura, M.E.
(1962) Some Aspects of Avicennas Theory of Gods Knowledge of
Particulars, Journal of the American Oriental
Society 82: 299-312. (This paper, along with those of Morewedge (1972) and Rahman
(1958), are seminal to contemporary understanding of Ibn Sinas thought.)
(1980)
Avicennas Proof from Contingency for Gods Existence in the Metaphysics of al Shifa, Medieval Studies 42: 337-52. (A
clear exposition of the proof.)
* Morewedge, P
(1972) Philosophical Analysis and Ibn Sinas Essence-Existence
distinction. Journal of the American Oriental
Society 92: 425-35. (A welcome explanation of the
implications of a distinction central to Ibn
Sinas proof of Gods existence.)
Nasr, S. H.
(1996) Ibn Sinas Oriental Philosophy, in S.H. Nasr and O. Leaman (eds) History of Islamic Philosophy, London: Routledge,
ch. 17, 247-51. (Concise and interesting defence of the idea that Ibn Sina really did have
distinctive system of mystical philosophy.)
Rahman, F.
(1958) Essence and Existence in Avicenna, Medieval and Renaissance Studies 4: 1-16. (A
version also appears in Hamdard Islamicus 4 (1):
3-14. The paper considers the philosophical usefulness of the distinction of essence from
existence.)
SALIM KEMAL